Clark's God and Evil: The Problem Solved.
Reviewed by Dr. W. Gary Crampton
Copyright 1999 © First Presbyterian Church of Rowlett
In 1961, the first edition of Gordon Clark’s Religion, Reason and Revelation,
[1] was published. It was at that time, and still is, a classic in the field of
Christian apologetics. Among those issues which Clark deals with in this
treatise are Christianity’s uniqueness, the place of logic in philosophy and
theology, the definition of faith, the usefulness and importance of language,
the inerrancy of Scripture, the standard of ethics, and the problem of evil. A
biblical apologetic must be able “to give a defense to everyone who asks you to
give a rational account” regarding each of these matters (1 Peter 3:15). And Dr.
Clark does so in an admirable fashion.
Of the issues mentioned above, perhaps none is so difficult as the problem of
evil. Thomas Warren, for example, has written that “it is likely the case that
no charge has been made with a greater frequency or with more telling force
against theism of Judeo-Christian (biblical) tradition” than the complication of
the existence of evil.” [2] Even the biblical writers themselves address the
topic of God and evil. The prophet Habakkuk complained: “You [God] are of purer
eyes than to behold evil, and cannot look on wickedness. Why do you look on
those who deal treacherously, and hold your tongue when the wicked devours?”
(1:13). And Gideon contemplated: “O my lord, if the Lord is with us, why then
has all this [hardship] befallen us? (Judges 6:13).
If, according to the Bible, God, who is omnipotent and omnibenevolent, has
eternally decreed all that ever comes to pass, and if he sovereignly and
providentially controls all things in his created universe, how is he not the
author of evil? How can evil exist in the world? How do we justify the actions
of God in the midst of evil, suffering, and pain? This is the question of
“theodicy.” It has to do with the justification of the goodness and
righteousness of God in light of the evil in the world.
In his God and Evil: The Problem Solved, [3] which was originally Chapter Five
of Religion, Reason and Revelation, Gordon Clark accomplishes what many
theologians and philosophers have attempted and failed to do, i.e., explain the
problem of evil. As Clark has said, “whereas various other views disintegrate at
this point, the system known as Calvinism and expressed in the Westminster
Confession of Faith offers a satisfactory and completely logical answer” (7).
The answer as we will see, lies in our epistemological starting point: the Word
of God.
Throughout the centuries, there have been numerous non-Christian attempts to
deal with the matter of theodicy (7-12). Some, such as Mary Baker Eddy, have
simply denied that evil exists at all, i.e., it is illusory. Others, such as
John Stuart Mill and William Pepperell Montague, have opted for a finite god,
one who is limited in power. Hence, he cannot be blamed for the existence of
evil in the world.
Plato and the Zoroastrians, on the other hand, posited some form of ultimate
dualism. Good and evil coexist independently, thus accounting for the mixture of
good and evil in the world. Aristotle conceived of god as the Unmoved Mover, who
was not really concerned about the things of this world. This being the case,
the relation of Aristotle’s god to evil and the moral endeavors of men is
inconsequential.
These theories, of course, fall far short of a biblical theodicy. Scripture
clearly teaches that sin is not illusory (Genesis 3). Further, the God of
Scripture is no finite deity. He is the ex nihilo Creator and Sustainer of
heaven and earth (Genesis 1:1; Hebrews 1:1-3), who is very concerned with his
universe and the moral affairs of men (Exodus 20). Moreover, the God of
Scripture brooks no competition (Job 33:13), so that there can be no form of
ultimate dualism.
The great Christian philosopher Augustine, also pondered the theodicy issue. He
taught that since God created all things good, evil cannot have a separate or
independent existence. Evil is the absence of good, as darkness is the absence
of light. Evil is parasitic, in that it cannot exist apart from good.
This being so, said Augustine, evil cannot be the efficient cause of sin;
rather, it is a deficient cause in man. Evil is the result of man’s turning away
from the good commands of God to seek a lesser good: the will of the creature,
man. It is man, not God, who is the author of sin. This, though, is no solution
to the problem. As Clark states: “Deficient causes, if there are such things, do
not explain why a good God does not abolish sin and guarantee that men always
choose the highest good” (9).
Arminianism, as an ostensible Christian system, also fails to give us a biblical
theodicy (12-19). Arminian theologians attribute the problem of evil to the free
will of man. In his freedom, Adam chose to sin, apart from God’s will. Adam had
a “liberty of indifference” to the will of God. God merely permitted man to sin.
The idea of God’s merely “permitting” man to sin, however, is wholly unbiblical
and does not give us a solution (17-19). Clark explains: [4]
Somehow the idea of God’s permitting evil without decreeing it seems to absolve
God from the charge that he is the ‘author’ of sin, but one must be careful,
both with respect to the logic of the argument and to the full scriptural data.
God ‘permitted’ Satan to afflict Job; but since Satan could not have done so
without God’s approval, the idea of permission hardly exonerates God. Is perfect
holiness any more compatible with approving or permitting Satanic evil? If God
could have prevented, not only Job’s trials, but all the other sins and
temptations to which mankind is subject – if he foresaw them and decided to let
them occur – is he less reprehensible than if he positively decreed them? If a
man could save a baby from a burning house, but decided to ‘permit’ the baby to
burn, who would dare say that he was morally perfect in so deciding?
Such a view of permission and free will cannot coexist with God’s omnipotence.
Neither is the Arminian view of free will compatible with God’s omniscience,
because omniscience renders the future certain (31,32). If God foreknows all
things, then of necessity they will come to pass; otherwise, they could not be
“foreknown.” God foreknew, even foreordained, the crucifixion of his Son by the
hands of sinful men. Yet, according to Scripture the godless men who carried out
the act are responsible (Acts 2:22,23; 4:27,28). Could they have done
differently? Could Judas Iscariot not have betrayed Jesus Christ? To ask the
questions is to answer them; of course not (41). The God of the Bible, writes
Clark, “determines or decrees every action” (20). Hence, Arminianism’s attempted
refuge in free will is both “futile” and “false; for the Bible consistently
denies [the Arminian view of] free will” (19).
Reformed theology does not disavow the fact that Adam (and all men after him)
had a “free will” in the sense of “free moral agency” (13-16). [5] All men have
freedom of choice in this sense of the term. Men of necessity choose to do what
they want to do; in fact, they could not do otherwise. What Reformed theology
does deny is that man has the “freedom of indifference.” His freedom to choose
is always governed by factors: his own intellections, habits, and so forth. Of
course, all choices are subject to the eternal decrees of God.
As mentioned, this is not only true of post-fall man. It was also true of Adam
prior to Genesis 3. The major difference is that post-fall man, who still
maintains his free moral agency, has lost that which Adam originally possessed:
the ability to choose what God requires. Fallen man, in his state of “total
depravity,” always chooses to do that which he desires, but his sin nature
dictates that he always chooses evil (Romans 3:9-18; 8:7,8; Ephesians 4:17-19).
This “ability” to choose good is only restored through regeneration.
Man, then, is never indifferent in his willing to do anything. God has
determined all things that will ever come to pass. Yet, this does not undermine
the responsibility of man. There is no disjunction here. The Westminster
Confession of Faith (3:1; 5:2,4) correctly states that (26-28):
God from all eternity did, by the most wise and holy counsel of his own will,
freely and unchangeably ordain whatsoever comes to pass: yet so, as thereby
neither is God the author of sin, nor is violence offered to the will of the
creatures, nor is the liberty or contingency of second causes taken away, but
rather established….Although, in relation to the foreknowledge and decree of
God, the first cause, all things come to pass immutably and infallibly; yet, by
the same providence, he ordereth them to fall out according to the nature of
second causes, either necessarily, freely, or contingently….The almighty power,
unsearchable wisdom, and infinite goodness of God, so far manifest themselves in
his providence, that it extendeth itself even to the first fall, and all other
sins of angels and men, and that not by a bare permission, but such as hath
joined with it a most wise and powerful bounding, and otherwise ordering and
governing of them, in a manifold dispensation, to his own holy ends; yet so as
the sinfulness thereof proceedeth only from the creature, and not from God; who,
being most holy and righteous, neither is nor can be the author or approver of
sin.
God, says the Confession, is the sovereign first cause of all things, many of
which occur through the free acts of man, which are second causes. The end which
is decreed by God must never be separated from the means which he has also
decreed, as second causes. God, writes Clark, “does not arrange things or
control history apart from second causes….God does not decree apart from the
means. He decrees that the end shall be accomplished by means of the means.” [6]
And this is the reason, according to the Confession, that God is not to be
considered “the author or approver of sin.” God is the sovereign first cause of
sin, but he is not the author of sin. Only second causes sin (51).
This view taught by the Westminster divines is the Calvinistic concept of
“determinism” (19-21). The word determinism often carries with it an evil
connotation, but this should not be the case. In actuality, determinism
expresses a very biblical and high view of God, and it gives us the only
plausible theodicy. God determines or decrees every event of history and every
action of man.
Moreover, whatever God decrees is right simply because he decrees it; God can
never err (48,53). God, says the Scripture, answers to no one (Job 33:13). He is
the lawgiver (Isaiah 33:22); man is under the law. God is accountable to no one;
he is ex lex (“above the law”). The Ten Commandments are binding on man, not
God. And the only precondition for responsibility is a lawgiver, in this case
God. In Dr. Clark’s words: “Man is responsible because God calls him to account;
man is responsible because the supreme power can punish him for disobedience”
(54). Thus, man is necessarily responsible for his sin, and God is completely
absolved of being the author of sin.
The determinism taught in the Westminster Confession of Faith is not the same
thing as fatalism (36-42). In fatalism, god, or the gods, or the Fates,
determine all things, while man remains completely passive. Hence, logically man
cannot be responsible for his sinful actions. In biblical determinism, on the
other hand, God sovereignly determines all things, but he also holds man
responsible, because man and his ‘freely chosen” sinful actions are the second
causes through which things are determined to occur.
But someone will ask: “Is not murder sin and contrary to the will of God? How
can it be that God wills it?” The answer, says Clark (35,36), is found in
Deuteronomy 29:29: “The secret things belong to the Lord our God, but those
things which are revealed belong to us and to our children forever, that we may
do all the words of this law.” Here Moses distinguishes between the decretive
will (“secret things”) and the preceptive will (“those things which are
revealed”). God’s preceptive will is found in Scripture. Therein we learn what
God requires of man. God’s decretive will, on the other hand, is the cause of
every event. Man is responsible for the preceptive, not the decretive will. In
the example used earlier, God from all eternity decreed Christ’s crucifixion,
yet when it was carried out by the hands of sinful men, it was contrary to the
moral law, i.e., God’s preceptive will.
Conclusion
In the opinion of this reviewer, in Gordon Clark’s God and Evil: The Problem
Solved, we have the best work available on the subject at hand. The author shows
us that standing on the rock foundation of the Word of God (Matthew 7:24,25), we
have an answer to the theodicy issue. It is all a matter of one’s epistemic
base. With the Bible as the axiomatic starting point, the existence of evil is
really not the problem it is made out to be. God, who is altogether holy and who
can do no wrong, sovereignly decrees evil things to occur for his own good
purposes (Isaiah 45:7). And just because he decreed it, it is right. As stated
by the Reformer Jerome Zanchius: [7]
The will of God is so the cause of all things, as to be itself without cause,
for nothing can be the cause of that which is the cause of everything….Hence we
find every matter resolved ultimately into the mere sovereign pleasure of
God….God has no other motive for what he does than ipsa voluntas, his mere will,
which will itself is so far from being unrighteous that it is justice itself.
It is good, then, that sin exists. God has decreed it and it is working for the
ultimate: his glory.
--------------------------------------------------------
[1] Gordon H. Clark, Religion, Reason and Revelation (The Trinity Foundation,
1986 [1961]).
[2] Thomas B. Warren, Have Atheists Proved There is No God? (Nashville: Gospel
Advocate Co., 1972), vii.
[3] Gordon H. Clark, God and Evil: The Problem Solved (The Trinity Foundation,
1996). The pagination used in the body of this review is from Clark’s book. Much
of the material contained in this review is a revision of an article published
earlier in The Trinity Review. See W. Gary Crampton, “A Biblical Theodicy,” The
Trinity Review (January 1999).
[4] Gordon H. Clark, First Corinthians (The Trinity Foundation, 1975, 1991),
156,157.
[5] See also Gordon H. Clark, What Do Presbyterians Believe? (Phillipsburg, New
Jersey: Presbyterian and Reformed, 1956, 1965), 105-112.
[6] Ibid., 38.
[7] Cited in Gordon H. Clark, An Introduction to Christian Philosophy (The
Trinity Foundation, 1993), 113,114.